Wednesday, April 23, 2014

More on Piketty's Capital

Robert Solow presents a very clear explication of Piketty's arguments at New Republic. Capital in the 21st Century is, as Solow says, a serious book.

Brad DeLong rounds up the criticism of the book. I have been groping for a way to describe its reception among economists, which is that there are a number of criticisms with parts of it, but that no one I've read feels that it's in any way stupid or misguided. In other words, it is a serious  book. As Brad says, everyone agrees with about 70%, disagrees with 10-20% and isn't sure about another 10-20% but can't agree on which parts to agree or disagree with. There are several useful critiques, and several critiques which argue from derp, from which to choose.

Tyler Cowen is less laudatory and more critical, but still recommends reading the book. Suresh Naidu also has an interesting take.

From a cultural perspective, it's weird to see a dense tome on economic distribution and growth reach number one bestseller status. I haven't seen Piketty on any of the national talk shows yet. I dread that day.

Tuesday, April 15, 2014

Thomas Piketty - Capital in the 21st Century

Distributional effects of the current economic system have received growing interest as the distribution of income and wealth within the largest economies has grown steeper. It seems that this month, Capital in the 21st Century is on the bedside table of every economist I know, as Michael Lewis's book is on the table of every trader. And as with Flash Boys, everyone's has a problem or two with Piketty's theses, while the consensus is that it's an important book even after taking the flaws into account.

Brad DeLong's "Finger exercises" provide a simple model to play with, and begins with a discussion of four different possible return rates (r) that might relate to the growth rate (g) in Piketty's models. He then looks at the levels of r, g, and wealth to income (W/Y); the results of the model suggest that at least to some extent, the inverse relationship of return rates to capital and accumulation of wealth does in fact hold.

James K. Galbraith's review provides a number of interesting critiques, and finds that while the book contains good information on "flows of income, transfers of wealth and the distribution of financial resources in some of the world's wealthes countries," it does less well in proposing remedies appropriate to the times, and in clarifying the various meanings of "capital"; he also appears to muddle the precedents of the growth model he uses to drive his argument.
[T]he argument of the critics was not about Keynes, or fluctuations. It was about the concept of physical capital and whether profit can be derived from a production function. In desperate summary, the case was three-fold. First: one cannot add up the values of capital objects to get a common quantity without a prior rate of interest, which (since it is prior) must come from the financial and not the physical world. Second, if the actual interest rate is a financial variable, varying for financial reasons, the physical interpretation of a dollar-valued capital stock is meaningless. Third, a more subtle point: as the rate of interest falls, there is no systematic tendency to adopt a more “capital-intensive” technology, as the neoclassical model supposed. 
In short, the Cambridge critique made meaningless the claim that richer countries got that way by using “more” capital. In fact, richer countries often use less apparent capital; they have a larger share of services in their output and of labor in their exports—the “Leontief paradox.” Instead, these countries became rich—as Pasinetti later argued—by learning, by improving technique, by installing infrastructure, with education, and—as I have argued—by implementing thoroughgoing regulation and social insurance. None of this has any necessary relation to Solow’s physical concept of capital, and still less to a measure of the capitalization of wealth in financial markets. 
There is no reason to think that financial capitalization bears any close relationship to economic development. Most of the Asian countries, including Korea, Japan, and China, did very well for decades without financialization; so did continental Europe in the postwar years, and for that matter so did the United States before 1970. 
And Solow’s model did not carry the day. In 1966 Samuelson conceded the Cambridge argument!
DeLong finds fault with Galbraith's critique, and Galbraith responds in the comments on DeLong's post. Chris Bertram reviews Rawls' Economic Justice in light of Piketty over on the Crooked Timber group blog. Paul Krugman has a laudatory review of the book up at the NYRB.

*
 

My own first impression is to think that it would be quite difficult to maintain a return on capital much in excess of the growth rate in cases where capital provides nearly all of the factor input of production, at least for the time periods we're talking about (50+ years). I could be mistaken, otherwise if r-g is large for any substantial length of time, then the quantity of capital would greatly exceed the entire output of the economy of which the capital is a part. Mathematically, these two growth rates have to converge as one becomes closer to another. Moreover, we would also expect that r would fall before that, due to diminishing returns. Piketty's exploding models, in which one factor totally predominates seems less appealing than some kind of pendulum model.

We are in a second Gilded Age, according to the evidence, and the question is what to do about it, and how bad might it get?Rather than raising the income tax to confiscatory levels as Piketty reommends, the most promising policy prescriptions available to us at this time seem to be to neutralize the favorable tax treatment of dividends and capital gains relative to wage income, to invest in public goods (both tangible and intangible), and to strengthen the social safety net.

Some questions I'm still thinking about: If wealth and income inequality are increasing in certain economies, but moderating globally, how much of the argument still holds? Has Piketty chosen the correct definition of r? Is Noah Smith correct in saying that this is just a restatement of the robots vs. globalization argument?

Monday, April 07, 2014

Giordano Bruno


For here is a philosophy that opens the senses, contents the spirit, glorifies the intellect, and produces the humane and true state of blessings that humanity desires, consists through balance, frees from care and pacifies sorrow, causes one to rejoice in the present and not to fear the future; for that Providence or fate or chance in life which determines our course through our particular vicissitudes neither wants nor permits us to know about one thing without ignorance of another, so that at first glance, we are always doubtful and perplexed. But, when we consider more profoundly the being and substance of the universe in which we immutably dwell, we see that neither we nor any real substance truly dies; for nothing is diminished in its substance, but all things that travel in infinite space change in aspect. And since we are all subject to the same Ultimate Efficient Cause, we should not believe, expect or hope otherwise than that, since everything comes from good, all is good, for the good and to the good; from good, through good, to good; anyone who believes the contrary apprehends nothing but what is present, as the goodness of a building is not manifest to one who sees only a tiny piece of it, like a stone affixed with a bit of cement to a garden wall, but which is visible  to one who sees the whole inside and out, who has the ability to see how each part converses with all the others. We have no fear that what has accumulated in this world could, through the vehemence of some errant spirit, or the wrath of Jove’s thunderbolt, be dispersed through this little sepulcher or cupola of the heavens, or shaken or scattered like dust throughout this starry mantle; and in no other way could nature be made to empty itself of subsistence, except when to our eyes it appears that air compressed within the concavity of a bubble vanishes on release, because there is nothing known in the world where one thing does not always succeed another, nor is there some ultimate deep of the world where being is finally dispersed into nonbeing by the Maker’s hand. There are no ends, boundaries, limits or walls which defraud or deprive us of the infinite multitude of things. Therefore, the earth and sea are fecund, therefore the sun burns forever, eternally supplying fuel for the voracious flames, as vapors feed diminished seas, therefore the infinite perpetually bears forth new material.

Giordano Bruno
On the Infinite, the Universe and the Worlds
Prefatory Epistle